Much is known concerning reverse mathematics for real analysis and the topology of complete separable metric spaces. Some of the inspiration for this comes from recursive analysis [25] and Bishop-style constructivism [2]. We shall not discuss those connections here, but see my book [32] for more information.
In Giusto/Simpson [11] we presented a rather thorough reverse mathematics discussion of various notions of closed set, and of various forms of the Tietze extension theorem for real-valued continuous functions on closed sets, in compact metric spaces. The purpose of this section is to call attention to one open problem left over from that paper.
Let X be a compact metric space. For concreteness we may take
X=[0,1], the unit interval. In
we define
to
be closed if it is the complement of a sequence of open balls;
separably closed if it is the closure of a sequence of points;
located if the distance function d(x,K) exists as a
continuous real-valued function on X; weakly located if the
predicate d(x,K)>r is
(allowing parameters, of course).
C(X) denotes the separable Banach space of continuous
real-valued functions on X which have a modulus of uniform
continuity. The strong Tietze theorem for K is the statement
that every
extends to some
.
See [11] for details.
Known results from [11] are:
It is known from [11] that (3) and (4) are provable in
and not provable in
.
There is a partial reversal: (3) or (4)
implies the DNR axiom over
.
We shall outline the proof of
this below. But first we discuss the DNR axiom.
The DNR axiom says: For every
there exists
which is diagonally nonrecursive relative to A,
i.e.,
for all
.
Here
is the set of
natural numbers. It would be possible to restate the DNR axiom in a
combinatorial way, not involving recursion theory, but we shall not do
so here.
The DNR axiom is known to be weaker than
(
weak
König's lemma). Indeed, the DNR axiom is provable in the strictly
weaker system
(
weak weak König's lemma) which
arises in connection with reverse mathematics for measure theory. (See
[32, §X.1], [11], [4].) Because of Kumabe's
result [21], it seems likely that the DNR axiom is strictly
weaker than
.
Recursion theorists can understand these variants of weak König's
lemma in terms of separating sets, recursively bounded classes, etc. Thus there is a close connection with Jockusch's talk
at this conference. In descending order we have:
We shall now end this section with an outline of the proof that the strong Tietze theorem for closed, separably closed subsets of [0,1]implies the DNR axiom.
We may as well assume that weak König's lemma fails. For each nlet In be the closed interval
[1/22n+1,1/22n]. Since weak
König's lemma fails, the Heine/Borel covering lemma fails, so let
(ank,bnk),
,
be a covering of In by open intervals
with no finite subcovering. We may assume that these coverings are
disjoint from one other.
If
is defined, let sn be the least s such that
is defined, and put
Define a real-valued continuous function
on K, as
follows. First let pi(x),
,
be a fixed, one-to-one,
recursive enumeration of
,
the ring of polynomials with
rational coefficients in one indeterminate, x. Using this, define
and, for
and
,
if
for some
,
otherwise.
It can be shown that
.
By the strong Tietze theorem for K, let
be an extension of
from
K to all of [0,1]. By Weierstrass polynomial approximation in
,
let
pin(x),
,
be a sequence of polynomials
such that
for all n. It is not difficult to show that the
function
given by f(n)=in is DNR.
By relativizing the above to an arbitrary
,
we get a
function that is DNR relative to A. This completes the proof.
Note: Recursion theorists may want to view the above as a standard
diagonal construction leading to a recursive counterexample to (4).
However, from the viewpoint of reverse mathematics, there seems to be
something unusual going on here. Usually, a recursive counterexample
leads to a reversal to
or
,
but in this instance all we
seem to get is a reversal to the DNR axiom.